Biography

Society as a Work of Art

A Really-Possible Public Sphere?

Salvaging Modernism

A Residual Sunday

Whose City? Whose Culture?

   Bibliography
   

 
 
Malcolm Miles
 
A RESIDUAL SUNDAY

This paper is a short version of the first part of a chapter for a forthcoming book, and paper delivered to the 7th international conference of the Utopian Studies Society, Tarragona, July 5th-8th, 2006. The later part of the chapter, not given here, deals with Seurat and Anarchism.
 

Introduction

This paper links Ernst Bloch's utopian idea of a residual Sunday, from The Principle of Hope [1959] (1986), with two paintings by George Seurat: Une Baignade (Asnières) (1883-84, London, National Gallery) and Un dimanche à la Grande Jatte (1885, Chicago, Art Institute), which I read as utopian images produced in an Anarchist milieu.

The argument is necessarily interpretive and speculative. Bloch is dismissive of Seurat but did not as far as I know see either painting in the original. Nor could he have seen them together since both left Europe in the early 1920s. Bloch and Seurat had different national and class backgrounds. Bloch was from a petit-bourgeois family in the provincial town of Ludwigshafen, Germany, and Seurat from a bourgeois family in metropolitan Paris. Their formative years were spent in different academic milieux, Bloch attending Georg Simmel's private colloquium in Berlin and then becoming part of Max Weber's circle in Heidelberg (Geoghegan, 1996: 11) while Seurat attended the Academy des Beaux-Arts before joining an informal group of fellow ex-students, artists and critics in Paris. Nor could Bloch have engaged Seurat in intellectual conversation, being aged six when Seurat died in 1891 (aged 31). If there is a commonality it is that both went against the grain, Bloch writing sympathetically on popular culture when it was disdained by the Frankfurt School, and Seurat absorbing classicism and a feeling for imagined rather than perceived realities amid Impressionism (Leighton and Thomson, 1997: 14). This is anecdotal, hardly a basis for an academic paper. But...

My commentary hinges on remarks made by Bloch, almost in passing, in The Principle of Hope to effect that Seurat's La Grande Jatte is a parody of the utopian idea of a residual Sunday, cited as only as a negative foil to Manet's Le Déjeuner sur l'herbe (1863, Paris, Louvre). I question Bloch's reading of the work, seeing it rather as one of a pair of related images by Seurat (with the Baignade) depicting exactly the residual Sunday, or the life of perpetual ease, enjoyed in these paintings by the bourgeois and artisan classes. The case is supported, but not conclusively, by Seurat's link to a milieu of Anarchist leanings, including Paul Signac and Félix Fénéon. Why did Bloch miss the point? Or, what does this story of a connection which was not and could not have been made, this non-event, say about Bloch's idea of a residual Sunday and Seurat's utopian imagery?

Bloch's aesthetic sympathies are generally for Expressionism and cases of late 19th-century art, such as Cézanne, which he sees as its precedents. Seurat's cerebral approach does not coincide with his liking for gesture. But the situation is compounded by Bloch's eclecticism and an idiosyncratic writing style described by Vincent Geoghegan as constructing "a unique Blochian world with its own topography, systems and processes" (Geoghegan, 1996: 1) but also as "intimidating" and "forbidding" (Geoghegan, 1996: 2). Bloch includes such cases as he likes, and writes about them as vehicles for his ideas, not as an art historian. Volumes 2 and 3 of The Principle of Hope - he cites Seurat in Volume 2 - are taken by Ronald Aronson as "a torture to read" and "impossible to follow." (Aronson, 1991: 223, in Geoghegan, 1996: 2-3). It would be easy to be as dismissive of Bloch as he is of Seurat. It is more helpful, then, to ask what is gained from re-reading Bloch via Seurat and re-seeing Seurat via Bloch, an effort valid in terms of an insight held by both, if independently gained, of a world indisputably better in terms of human happiness and ease than that offered under capitalism. There are, obviously, some important differences between Bloch's utopianism, elaborated over almost 1,400 pages in The Principle of Hope, and Seurat's at best implicit utopianism given the absence of a published programmatic description of the works. Bloch is informed primarily by Marxism, Seurat by Anarchism, in particular by Peter Kropotkin. Yet Bloch attaches importance to the forming of ideas of utopia, not least in art; and the form the utopian world is given in Seurat's two monumental paintings cited above is both of inherent interest in context of utopian ideas in 19th-century social thought, and as a case of the cultural agency proposed by Bloch. Bloch argues, that is, that the arts give glimpses of utopia to educate an otherwise latent if universal hope. I see Seurat's paintings as doing exactly this (though most art historians refuse Seurat's Anarchism on the grounds of his reticence to speak about it).

I begin by setting out what Bloch says about Seurat and Manet, then contextualise this in terms of his theory of hope and art's utopian agency, and note his work on millenarianism. I look next at Seurat's two paintings to argue that one shows the artisan class and the other the middle classes at ease in what could be a residual (or perpetual) Sunday enabled by industrial-scale production's ending of the economic problem of scarcity. I link this, too, to the idea of a promesse du bonheur, derived from Baudelaire, stated by Herbert Marcuse in an essay on French literature under the German Occupation (Marcuse, 1998: 199-214). Finally I ask what insights are made available by comparing the approaches taken by Bloch and Seurat.


Bloch on Seurat

Bloch writes of Seurat's painting La Grande Jatte, in Volume 2 of The Principle of Hope,
This picture is a single mosaic of boredom, a masterpiece of the longingly unsuccessful and distanced element in the dolce far niente. The picture portrays a bourgeois Sunday morning on an island in the Seine in the vicinity of Paris, and in fact: it now portrays this solely in a scornful way. Figures rest in the foreground with vacant faces, the group of others forms for the most part wooden verticals, like puppets from the toy-box, intensively preoccupied with strolling stiffly about. Then there is the pale river, with sailing boats, a rowing regatta, pleasure steamers, a background which despite its fun rather seems to belong to Hades than the sun. There is sheer hapless idleness in the picture, in its light matt and watery space, in the expressionless brooding. There is the Land of Cockaigne here, too, but such that with the working world every world, indeed every object seems to fade into watery tepidness. The result is bottomless boredom ... (Bloch, 1986: 814).
Later he adds, "The memory of the Sunday misery which Seurat painted in his promenade piece ..." (Bloch, 1986: 909); and argues that humanity can be liberated from false utopia, as in the "Devil's blessing" of La Grande Jatte (Bloch, 1986: 920), only by the introduction of a classless society. Seurat depicts artisans and the bourgeoisie in different drawing styles, hence not a classless but a class-based society (in which he enjoyed a privileged position, his studies and later independence from the mainstream art market enabled by financial support from his father). But Bloch's comments are based only on La Grande Jatte. He may not have known of the Baignade, though there are figures other than the bourgeoisie in La Grande Jatte, and ludic elements such as children, monkeys, and musicians which Bloch ignores.


Bloch on Manet

For Bloch, Seurat's imagery is introduced as a negative foil to Manet's, for him more direct, utopianism. Of Le déjeuner sur l'herbe he says,
... a relaxing day of enjoyment, a day of aesthetic pleasure ...the garden of Epicurus gathers and assembles. Soft light, as only Impressionism could create it, flows through the trees, surrounds the two couples, the naked woman and the one undressing to bathe, the dark male figures. What is portrayed is an extraordinarily French, extraordinarily lingering situation, full of innocence, supreme ease, unobtrusive enjoyment of life, and carefree seriousness. (Bloch, 1986: 813).
This innocence has no currency after feminist reconstructions of cultural histories (Betterton, 1987; Pollock, 1988). Janet Wolff (1989) asks why there are no flâneuses in modern literature, and just as the masculine flâneur gazes at poor or lonely people as representations of himself but at women as objects of desire, so the women in Manet's painting are there to serve the gaze of the men. They are artists' models and not bohemians, although Manet does in part critique the gaze in his painting Olympia (1863, Paris, Louvre).

Bloch cites Giorgione's Fête Champêtre as precedent, seeing the Déjeuner sur l'herbe as preserving a Renaissance echo (without the golden light) in "an aristocratic bohemia." (Bloch, 1986: 813). The dark, dressy clothes of Manet's male figures indicate a bohemia independent of social norms, but also, in Bloch's comment, a regressive aspect of bohemianism in its nostalgic glance to an aristocratic (pre-revolutionary) past. And although the art of the 1880s and 1890s was characterised by political disengagement and adoption of the artist's or writer's own state of psyche as subject matter, the seeds of disengagement are there in the 1860s in a Baudelarian ennui in face of a remodelling of Paris as a bourgeois city by Haussmann, before the defeat of cultural radicalism in the crushing of the Paris Commune in 1871. Seurat paints after that point, though in a politicised milieu and after the coded political comment of Impressionism. But his figures evidently represent class while Manet's presume to be déclassé. But if that de-classification, so to speak, rests on a nostalgic aristocraticism this is not a classless society.

Bohemianism allowed people from different class backgrounds to mix in certain circumstances, in cafés and artists' and writers' gatherings, for instances, but did not cancel class divisions. Neither were bohemian artists and writers, or students, generally free from the economic structures and exchange mechanisms of a capitalist society. But if bohemianism offered a model of a society within but distanced from the dominant society, this may be a model for what became, a few decades later, the autonomy of modern art. In critical theory, Adorno and Marcuse discuss the limits of an aesthetic dimension in transforming social life, in their cases - unlike Bloch's - from comfortable backgrounds. But I wonder if, for Bloch, though he is not explicit, bohemianism as depicted by Manet in the 1860s is a proto-representation of the state of ease which he identifies as the end of social transformation. He calls this a residual Sunday, a day of ease which, in freedom, is everyday. Art allows glimpses of it.


The Residual Sunday

Bloch puts forward the idea of a residual Sunday in a section of The Principle of Hope titled 'Wishful Landscape Portrayed in Painting, Opera, Literature' (1986: 794-838). He cites van Eyck, Brueghel, Giorgione, Vermeer, de Hooch, Rembrandt, Watteau, Gauguin, and Cézanne as well as Manet and Seurat. He begins from the idea that expression shapes an inner voice, following his argument throughout The Principle of Hope that hope is shaped in moments of its coming into consciousness. What begins as a latent content of consciousness first known in daydreams becomes more consciously directed (as daydreams are more directed than night dreams), and is educated through the act of articulation, or of recognition in a suitable vehicle, and hence brought closer to real-possibility. This might be called the work of hope, to which the work of reading art could be parallel.

Bloch begins the section, "It leads nowhere at all merely to feel in a beautiful way." (Bloch, 1986: 794). This echoes a passage in Volume 1 in which the real and artificial are juxtaposed:
We say of the beautiful that it gives pleasure ... But its reward does not end there, art is not food. For it remains even after it has been enjoyed, even in the sweetest cases it hangs over into a land which is 'pictured ahead'. The wishful dream goes out here into what is indisputably better ... Only: is there anything more in what has been shaped in this way than a game of appearance? (Bloch, 1986: 210).
In 'Wishful Landscape Portrayed' Bloch adds,
A picture is therefore also heard ... it narrates what we see in it. And first of all in a friendly way, what is colourful as such has a cheerful effect. (Bloch, 1986: 795).
The last phrase has particular relevance to Seurat's adoption of a theory of colour in which the colours red to yellow in the colour circle evoke a happy mood. But Bloch's first reference to art here is to Dutch 17th-century genre painting, and to the objects depicted rather than the mode of depiction or pictorial language of the work. Bloch says little about how the manner of representation speaks the content of a work as much as the subject matter, except in his description of Cézanne (see below).

Bloch describes an interior by de Hooch, making the subject-matter metaphorical,
A junk shop of happiness ... the effect here of a treasure chamber ... [where] Nothing but domestic everyday life is painted ... but for all its nearness it is also presented ... as a sailor may see it from a distance when he thinks of home. (Bloch, 1986: 796).
Utopia is equated with the recovery of a potentially better world, always extant but latent, of which, because it was there before as well as eventually, the attainment can be likened to a home-coming - recovery of Heimat, redemption which infuses the present with its radical goodness from afar. Suspension of time may enable Bloch to read art history outside its chronology - as a timeless continuity taking forms inflected but not determined by historically specific conditions. Again, there is a parallel with art's autonomy as site of a timeless aesthetic in modernism. But I think there is something particular about Bloch's idea of redemption from after history, as it were. He ends The Principle of Hope, "there arises in the world something which shines into the childhood of all and in which no one has yet been: homeland." (Bloch, 1986: 1376). Peter Blickle, in a study of Heimat, gives a slightly different translation: "... that which shines everyone into his or her childhood ..." (Blickle, 2002: 131). Blickle continues,
Heimat shines into childhood. But to do so it has to exist outside of it. Heimat is not childhood itself. It is that which is seen to lie in childhood from an adult point of view. ... a place and a source of gentle light, light that shines everyone into his or her childhood ... (ibid).
He adds from wider references that it has a "softly glowing, intermingled aura of innocence and authenticity ..." (ibid) - which to me brings Seurat's softly glowing paintings to mind.

Setting aside a discussion of Heimat which could constitute a chapter itself, for Bloch, art produces glimpses of this not-yet homeland in mediated images of a land without illness, wildness, loudness and disruptiveness, where "nor does it seem as if care itself could ever visit." (Bloch, 1986: 797). This is real life not art, but not-yet real-ised. Art prefigures it or points the way, and Bloch's next example - Watteau's Embarkation for Cythera - indicates its existence in times of oppression. There are three versions of the picture. Bloch states that the arrangement of the figures in the first is "still wooden" (Bloch, 1986: 797). Citing the second - Le Pèlerinage à Cythère (1717, Paris, Louvre - he sees a libidinal landscape,
dream and group formation ... the love-barque waits on the silver water, distant mountains stand in the twilight, invisibly but directly the night of the island influences the movement and fore-pleasure of the picture." (Bloch, 1986: 798).
He prefers this to the more ornate third version in Berlin though in that the combination of "rosy-red and sky-blue around the sail is emphatic sweetness ... a flag of the promise sent across by the island of love." (Bloch, 1986: 798). An inference from the comparison of these versions is that Bloch, at times, pays close attention to artworks. But I do not know which of Watteau's paintings he saw in the original, and if he did see them in Paris and Berlin, which is entirely possible, whether he writes about them from memory or with the aid of art book reproductions. Bloch cites Rubens' Garden of Love (Madrid, Prado), for instance, as a superior precedent for Watteau's paintings of Cythera, showing "repose, almost habit of happiness" (Bloch, 1986: 798), but he did not go to Madrid.

Whether Bloch wrote from primary or secondary sources may seem inconsequential. But if his negative reading of La Grand Jatte was based on seeing the work in reproduction - it was acquired for the Art Institute in Chicago in 1924 (Herbert, 2004: 12) - it is appropriate to pursue the point because, firstly, Bloch's complaint in response to Lukács' critique of Expressionism is that Lukács relied on literary reviews and introductions, failing to get to the core of the matter when "His material is second-hand from the outset" (Bloch, 1980: 19); but secondly, since the two paintings were purchased by different museums in different continents it has not been possible to see them as the pair on which my own interpretation in depends, this puts me in the same position as Bloch puts Lukács yet in which Bloch, too, might be in his dismissal of Seurat.

Moving on, Bloch's idea of a residual Sunday derives from Pieter Brueghel's Land of Cockaigne: "an eternal Sunday, which is one because there is no sign of any treadmill", followed via "a leap in manners, attitude and spirit" by the "epicurean happiness" of Manet's Déjeuner sur l'herbe (Bloch, 1986: 813) with its "supreme ease, unobtrusive enjoyment of life, and carefree seriousness." (Bloch, 1986: 813). He asserts that depicting scenes of ease was difficult in the 19th century, when the restrictive mentality of bourgeois life curtailed articulation of such content, Seurat's paintings conforming to this limitation. But it is Cézanne who above all depicts the utopian home-coming, through the objects of the bourgeois world, or, "those in which even in the bourgeois world a positive image of Sundayness was still possible." (Bloch, 1986: 815). Cézanne paints a world of simple things, in which the ease is laconic. Bloch writes,
Cézanne transforms even his still lifes into places in which things are rigorous and sedentary, in which happy ripeness has settled. What has been plucked in these pictures, the apples, lemons, oranges, are not fruits any more, although they are painted as such with extreme care and precision, they are witnesses to a heavy contentment, brought from Hesperidean landscapes on to the tablecloth of the feast day. (Bloch, 1986: 815).
Cézanne's landscapes with bathers, too, are utopian images. What, then, is the problem in Seurat? Is it his overtly modern, quasi-scientific visual language, the aspect of his work most cited by favourable critics in the late 1880s (Herbert, 2004: 125-130)? Or his adoption of a style informed by neo-classicism, which may have seemed to Bloch too close to the classicism which informs an aspect of Socialist Realism? Perhaps Seurat lacks the passion Bloch sees in Cézanne, whom he calls in Spirit of Utopia, "the last great modern stylist", in whose work "even more deeply than in van Gogh, the Expressionist revolution is evident." (Bloch, 2000: 31). Bloch continues, in a passage seemingly revised as the extract above,
for this is no longer fruit, nor is it fruit modeled in paint; instead all imaginable life is in them, and if they were to fall, a universal conflagration would ensue, to such an extent are these still lifes already heroic landscapes, so loaded are these paintings with mystical gravity and a yet unknown, nameless mythology. (Bloch, 2000: 31).
Cézanne might not have put it like that. Bloch, putting Cézanne in the pre-history of Expressionism, reads into his still lifes an apocalyptic aspect. But while Expressionism has a millenarian aspect, as in Wassily Kandinsky's theory - Über das geistige in der Kunst (published in 1911) - it is hard to find in Cézanne's still lifes, landscapes, or timeless bathers. If is found in one of Bloch's other abiding interests, however: millenarianism.


Seurat's Residual Sunday

Seurat's Baignade was his first large-scale composition, or salon painting, completed in 1884 (with additions in 1887) after many preliminary studies of figures and the work's site on an island in the Seine. It is in a tradition of monumental paintings which includes the academicist works familiar in the annual Salons, and Courbet's The Studio (1855, Paris, Louvre), a statement of revolutionary content informed by the utopian social theory of Charles Fourier. Seurat's development in the years prior to the Baignade was, too, influenced by his art education, in which he encountered both images and theories. Among the former were two mural copies of Piero della Francesca's Battle of Heraclius and Chroesus and Discovery and Proof of the Cross (both c.1460, Arezzo, San Francesco) installed by Charles Blanc in the Ecole des Beaux-Arts in 1872 and 1873 (Smith, 1997: 12). John Leighton and Richard Thomson see the Baignade as a departure from conventional idealization in late 19th-century French art, leaving aside the forms of Greek sculpture and the smooth brushwork of Salon artists like Bouguereau and Merson (Leighton and Thomson, 1997: 126). Seurat was drawn towards Piero's work (though seeing it in a secondary source), anyway: Paul Smith remarks that the hat worn by the male youth on the river bank in the Baignade is "borrowed from the sleeping soldier in Piero's Resurrection", also citing Blanc on the spiritually uplifting quality of Greek art and the "hieratic idiom" of Puvis de Chavannes (Smith, 1997: 12). For Blanc the uplift was moral. I argue that for Seurat it is aesthetic and political.

This suggests the making of a genealogy linking Piero, Puvis de Chavannes and Seurat. Smith adds that Seurat not only saw Puvis' work but depicted his Le pauvre pêcheur in Paysage avec 'Le pauvre pêcheur' (c.1879-1880, Paris, Collection Huguette Berès). Seurat may even have been Puvis' assistant, squaring up his murals and working alongside the Symbolist painter Edmond Aman-Jean. Smith argues that Puvis was an idealist exemplifying Blanc's theoretical position, but a modern idealist outside the academic system to be "almost regarded as an avant-garde painter." (Smith, 1997: 14). So, another genealogy emerges linking Puvis and Seurat to Signac and, in the early 1900s, to Matisse in depictions of a state of ease which Matisse calls Luxe (from Baudelaire's poem 'Invitation au voyage'). At first, this subject-matter may seem remote from political concerns and revolution. Yet Herbert Marcuse, in an essay on French literature under the German occupation in the 1940s, cites this poem as "in the face of a society based on the buying and selling of labor power, the absolute negation and contradiction ... and, at the same time, the utopia of real liberation." (Marcuse, 1998: 204). Marcuse elaborates, citing Eluard and Aragon, that sensuality "expresses the individual protest against the law and order of repression" (Marcuse, 1998: 204); and that the last of Eluard's 'Sept Poèmes d'amour en guerre' "comprises all the terror of fascism and all the hope of the revolution ..." (Marcuse, 1998: 206). The permeating content of this genre of love poetry, as of Baudelaire's work and by extension I would say images of Luxe, is the promesse du bonheur which to me appears close to the always-present even if latent hope which Bloch attempts to establish as equivalent to a Freudian drive.

The promesse du bonheur is not a moral quality. For Leighton and Thomson, Seurat both adopts and resists the idealisation taught by Blanc, which had a moral undertone. They note the absence of facial features in the Baignade, and that some characteristics may, in the interpretation of physiognomy of the day, indicate alcohol abuse and a physical vigour unmatched by intellectual ability, so that "the features of the central youth quite contradict the elevated serenity of his fellows' poses." (Leighton and Thomson, 1997: 126). This could be a rude, in the sense of rustic or homely, interruption of serenity. But to me the reading of real-life dis-ease is compatible with a reading of the painting as the artisan class taking its ease, in terms both of the fusion of individual features in a schematic treatment representing the reality of a social category, and of the contrast of a physical appearance denoting the impact of present conditions with a pictorial scheme representing liberation from such conditions. Leighton and Thomson say that when the painting is seen as a whole "its idealising nature becomes clearer." (Leighton and Thomson, 1997: 126). They also note that other artists, such as Jean-Charles Cazin, aroused controversy by depicting classical characters to look like street prowlers (Boulanger, G. (1885) A nos Elèves, p.7 in Leighton and Thomson, 1997: 126; fig. 152) in what seems a form of Baudelaire's characterization of the modern artist as a painter of modern life. The difference between Seurat and the Romantic, Realist or Naturalist artists of the mid century is that Seurat paints modern life as it could be, or, taking an inference from the stillness and monumentality of the work, as it always was in potential - a latently hoped-for world indisputably better than that of present restrictions.


REFERENCES
Adorno, T.W. (1997) Aesthetic Theory, trans. Hullot-Kentor, R., London, Athlone
Argüelles, J. A. (1972) Charles Henry and the Formation of a Psychophysical Aesthetic, Chicago, University of Chicago Press
Aronson, A. (1991) 'Review of The Principle of Hope', History and Theory, vol. 30, #2, pp.220-232
Betterton, R. (1987) Looking On: Images of Femininity in the Visual Arts and Media, London, Pandora
Blickle, P. (2002) Heimat: A Critical Theory of the German Idea of Homeland, Rochester (NY), Camden House
Bloch, E. [1938] (1980) 'Discussing Expressionism', in Bloch, E., Lukács, G., Brecht. B., Benjamin, W., and Adorno, T., (1980) Aesthetics and Politics, London, Verso
Bloch, E. [1959] (1986) The Principle of Hope, Cambridge (MA), MIT
Bloch, E. (1988) The Utopian Function of Art and Literature, trans. Zipes, F. and Mecklenburg, F., Cambridge (MA), MIT
Bloch, E. (1991) Heritage of Our Times, Cambridge, Polity
Bloch, E (1998) Literary Essays, trans. Joron, A. and others, Stanford (CA), Stanford University Press
Bloch, E. [1964] (2000) The Spirit of Utopia, Stanford, Stanford University Press
Geoghegan, V. (1996) Ernst Bloch, London, Routledge
Herbert, R.L. (2004) Seurat and the Making of La Grand Jatte, Chicago, Art Institute (with University of California Press)
Leighton, J. and Thomson, R. (1997) Seurat and the Bathers, London, National Gallery
Marcuse, H. (1998) Technology, War and Fascism, ed. Kellner, D., London, Routledge
Pollock, G. (1988) Vision and Difference: Femininity, Feminism and the Histories of Art, London, Routledge
Smith, P. (1997) Seurat and the Avant-Garde, New Haven (CT), Yale
Wolff, J. (1989) 'The Invisible Flâneuse: women and the Literature of Modernity', in Benjamin, A., ed. (1989) The Problems of Modernity: Adorno and Benjamin, London, Routledge, pp.141-156