|
|
 |
 |
Malcolm
Miles |
|
The end of modernity’s end?
This paper speculates that the process
which might be called the end of modernity has arrived at a potential conclusion
in the triumph of neoliberalism and the effective abandonment of the state as a
vehicle for the protection of the commonwealth (a term which I use conscious of
its association with the Protectorate and the English Revolution). This may be
obvious but I try to approach it via a connection between two quite separate
texts, one from art history and the other from critical theory. The first
argues that modernism (the art of late modernity) cannot be understood now
because the conditions of its production have become remote. The other argues
that the project of capital (the economics of late modernity) is total containment
of all aspects of human life in its mechanisms. Between loss and defeat,
however, emerges a strand of contingent thought which, while not an exit from
present social or environmental injustices re-casts the problem as more
conducive to an extrication of what I see as the utopian content of modernism
and modern philosophy from its wreck.
For the sake of argument, I locate
the end of modernity between the failure of revolt in Paris and other cities in
May, 1968, and today’s ubiquitous privatisation of space and marketisation of social organisation. The end of the end of
modernity, then, is market-totalitarianism and its most extant form, consumerism.
I am not concerned with arguments (widely rehearsed) about postmodernity or the
simulacra of late capitalism; instead, my underlying concern is that –
far from this being the end of history – history now enters uncharted
ground in terms of how the market’s accumulation of power-over and erasure of
the people’s power-to will be contested or refused as the outcomes of late
capitalism are seen to include global warming and routine abuses of human
rights. Looking back, a vision of a better life for all social classes is both a
relic of a lost past and, still, alluring as a future vision.

Context: consumerism and unreason
The 2007 financial services crisis
demonstrated capital’s flight into fancy and absence of self-regulation; yet
business-as-usual was the mantra of the day as states, residually providing
out-sourced governmental services to global capital, used public money to salvage
private banks. This was followed by austerity regimes which crippled the
economies of several countries to be met by mass demonstrations. The anonymous French
collective The Invisible Committee write that the West now resembles a tourist ‘lost
on the Mongolian plains … who clutches his credit card as his only lifeline.’
[1]
I wonder if that position has really been reached. Sociologist Colin Cremmin argues instead that, ‘Markets … are disembedded from society the more that commodities shape
our existence.’
[2]
Perceptions
are altered to suit market imperatives, and the tourist (or banker) waving a
credit card may be rescued by a car and driver, with a nice picnic in the boot.
An old proverb has been modified. Once it was: you will wait a long time on the
hillside before a roast duck flies into your mouth; now the duck arrives
complete with napkin and knife and fork, but only for the platinum elite. Cremmin admits that, with neoliberalism, the market is ‘a
juggernaut without a driver,’ which echoes The Invisible Committee; but this is
‘naturalised,’ he argues, by a culture of acceptance that is ‘pregnant with
opportunities for those who capitulate to its logic.’
[3]
Capitulation rests on a myth that there is no alternative to the way things
are, as if this is as a-historical as weather (which is not a-historical at all
in a period of climate change). For the non-elite, consumerism is enforced by
the global news-media-entertainment sector, masking a widening gap between the world’s richer and poorer
citizens, subsuming images of deprivation in advertising, and replacing
political choices with choices within
various manufactured wants. This introduces a social ordering of conformity to market
imperatives while brand-capitalism finds no disaster an obstacle to its pursuit
of profit.
[4]
After an era of liberal reform based on the pursuit of civic values and the
notional public sphere – which was to an extent contradicted by a
parallel rise in the concept of autonomy – a regime of surveillance
relegates individual and social rights to a lost Eden.
There are complexities, however, in
that both the modern idea of autonomy (whether in art or the rights of citizens,
including that of a refusal of the status quo) and the notion of consumer
choice rest on a problematic construct – the freedom of individuals to
act as they decide, or as they want under consumerism – inherited from
the seventeenth century. In liberal humanism, that is, the individual is free
and acts rationally. The characters acting parts on a proscenium stage seem to
determine the course of the plot (even if tragically), and stand in, as it
were, for the audience of educated individuals who would like to make such
freely determined choices in their own lives and social organisation under a
constitutional monarchy.
[5]
In the eighteenth century, bourgeois autonomy meant a freedom of commerce and
wealth accumulation against the interference of the (still mainly dynastic)
state. In the nineteenth century, dynastic states gave way to nation-states and
their institutions; regulation grew as a means of alleviating the worst effects
of market operations, acting (like the establishment of art museums) as a means
to prevent insurrection. Matthew Arnold saw a crisis when disagreements within
Christianity tended to discount the church as a vehicle for social cohesion,
arguing that in such conditions culture – pursued by the educated middle
classes – was the defence against social breakdown which he called
anarchy. Arnold was critical of an interpretation of being free as doing what
one likes, however, arguing that the middle class echoed the claims of the
eighteenth-century gentry: ‘Our middle class … with its maxim of every man for
himself in business, every man for himself in religion, dreads a powerful
administration which might somehow interfere with it.’
[6]
In the working class, Arnold saw a lack of
public consciousness: ‘Our masses are quite as raw and uncultivated as the
French; so far from their having the idea of public duty and of discipline’
that, for instance, they would rather ‘flee to the mines’ than join the army
during the Crimean War.
[7]
Arnold launches a tirade against the valuing of machinery but also against mass
political self-interest:
… this and that man, and this and that body
of men, all over the country, are beginning to assert and put in practice an
Englishman’s right to do what he likes; his right to march where he likes, meet
where he likes, enter where he likes, hoot as he likes, threaten as he likes,
smash as he likes. All this, I say, tends to anarchy; and though a number of
excellent people, and particularly my friends of the Liberal or progressive
party … are kind enough to reassure us by saying that these are trifles … - yet
one finds that one’s Liberal friends generally say this because they have such
faith in themselves and their nostrums, when they shall return, as the public
welfare requires, to place and power.
[8]
Ideally, if I can extend the
argument, cooperation between citizens would refine the agencies of government
to a point at which freedom is attained and the state is redundant when public
consciousness orders society benignly for all.
Millenarian visions of this kind have
recurred in European history, as in the anarchic society proclaimed by Abbot
Joachim of Fiore circa 1200: abolition of office and property; the Age of the
Spirit: immanent revolution.[9]
From another perspective, history
is struggle, an always-incomplete process shaped in resistance but inevitably
thereby burdened by the conditions it contests. Human freedom of action then leads
to conflict and perhaps repetition of trajectories of incompatible logic, as in
tragic drama. Marx fused materialism with idealism in a dialectic materialism
whereby human intervention inflects the conditions which condition people; but
all this is obsolete when consumerism imposes a single choice – to buy –
as a sole means for the expression or acquisition of identity. To buy what one
likes is in effect social membership and conceals conflicts between those who
can and cannot consume, or who enjoy unlimited mobility while the rest –
marginal others – are subject to increasing controls.[10]
This regime is enforced through the soft policing of mass culture and its
conjuring of admission tickets to the affluent society through the repeated purchases
of goods. This psychological pressure is applied parallel to the use of addictive
additives in food, and to an adrenalin-based addiction produced by a permanent
state of crisis in precarity. The outlook is bleak but
a premonition looms: part of the bleakness may be inherent in modernity itself.
Looking back
Art historian T. J. Clark writes in
Farewell to an Idea that, at the end
of the twentieth century, ‘the modernist past is a ruin, the logic of whose
architecture we do not remotely grasp’ as we have entered a new age when, it is
not lost but, ‘the modernity which modernism prophesied has finally arrived’ making
its forms of representation ‘unreadable.’
[11]
Modernity has reached its conclusion,
a kind of apotheosis of which its ruins are the sign. This requires explanation
in light of the
view that modernity is in ruins.
[12]
And Clark does explain:
Modernity means
contingency. It points to a social order which has turned from the worship of
ancestors and past authorities to the pursuit of a projected future – of
goods, pleasures, freedoms, forms of control over nature, or infinities of
information. This process goes along with a great emptying and sanitisation of
the imagination. … The phrase Max Weber borrowed from Schiller, ‘the
disenchantment of the world’ still seems to me to sum up this side of modernity
best.
[13]
This is the modern world of Enlightenment
which offers freedom from superstitions and rule by a mysterious, perhaps
implacable Fate; and equally an earlier form of being cast adrift as a
subject-citizen acting in an uncharted realm of agency (not waving a credit
card but seeking a map of the world, newly found to be a sphere). Critical
theorist Peter Sloterdijk argues that globalisation
began with the globe as a representation of a round Earth: ‘the new image of
the earth, the terrestrial globe, rose to become the central icon of the modern
world picture’ and from the first globe in 1492 to space exploration, ‘the
cosmological process of modernity is characterized by the changes of shape and
refinements of earth’s image in its diverse technical media.’
[14]
The globe resulted from the empirical knowledge of voyages around the Earth but
Sloterdijk claims it retained a metaphysical sense of
enclosure within a cosmos of spheres. By the 1850s, this is lost: ‘In panoramic
nature paintings, the aesthetic observation of the whole replaced its lost
safety in the vaulted universe. The beauty of physics made the tableau of the
holy circles dispensable.’
[15]
Citing the discoveries of geographer Alexander von Humbolt,
Sloterdijk continues,
This opening up
into the infinite heightens the risk of modern localizations. Humans know …
that they are contained or lost – which now amounts to virtually the same
thing – somewhere in the boundless. They understand that they can no
longer rely on anything except the indifference of homogenous infinite space.
The outside expands, ignoring the postulate of proximity in the human spheres,
as a foreign entity in its own right; its first and only principle seems to be
its lack of interest in humanity.
[16]
Nature, weather, space: all are indifferent
to human fate; a danger, I suggest, is that states and economic systems mimic indifference
through an agency which is not indifferent but follows vested interests.
Nonetheless, modernity entails acceptance of indifference, not merely as the
basis for aesthetic taste (or disinterest), but as the abandonment of reliance
on a supernatural power which might, subject to suitable observances and
offerings, bestow charity. Autonomy becomes being alone as wild nature is no
less radically other to human interests.
It is this state of being adrift in
free will which Adorno and Horkheimer
critique in Dialectic of Enlightenment.
[17]
They argue that Enlightenment is freedom from rule by arbitrary powers of
nature yet constitutes knowledge as power-over nature and human subjects. Enlightenment
abolishes myth and superstition in a dis-enchantment of the world but myth
reappears in other ways. One of these is the seeming imperative of power:
The rulers
themselves do not believe in any objective necessity, even though they
sometimes describe their concoctions thus. They declare themselves to be the
engineers of world history. Only the ruled accept as unquestionable necessity
the course of development that with every decreed rise in the standard of
living makes them so much more powerless. … The masses are fed and quartered …
their reduction to mere objects of the administered life, which preforms every
sector of modern existence including language and perception, represents
objective necessity, against which they believe there is nothing they can do.
[18]
A colloquial version of this is
that nothing withstands Progress regardless of what Progress brings. But, ‘true
revolutionary practice depends on the intransigence of theory in the face of
the insensibility with which society allows thought to ossify.’
[19]
Still, being cast adrift in the seas of
agency is daunting. Its utopian face is a benign collaborative world; its
dystopian face is domination by abstract (market) forces: ‘bourgeois economy
multiplied power through the mediation of the market’ and, ‘multiplied its
objects and powers to such an extent that … not just the kings, not even the
middle classes are no longer necessary, but all men.’
[20]
In the new bleakness, domination is normalised; Enlightenment descends into
‘wholesale deception of the masses.’
[21]
That
was written in the 1940s, haunted by the failure of the German Revolution of
1918-19 and the rise of fascism and its use of populist imagery and revivals of
myth: songs of crowns drowned in the Rhine, campfires and torchlight parades.
[22]
Clark asserts, too, ‘The disenchantment of the world is horrible … any mass
movement or cult figure that promises a way out of it will be clung to like
grim death.’
[23]
The
twentieth century exhibits the charisma of an aestheticised
politics; now we have celebrity. Against this fear, Adorno
and Horkheimer argue for a revision of Enlightenment
from within. And survivor Primo Levi writes,
There is no
rationality in the Nazi hatred … We cannot understand it, but we can and must
understand from where it springs, and we must be on our guard. If understanding
is impossible, knowing is imperative …
Everybody must
know, or remember, that when Hitler and Mussolini spoke in public, they were
believed, applauded, admired, adored like gods. They were charismatic leaders;
they possessed a secret power of seduction that did not proceed from the
credibility or the soundness of the things they said, but from the suggestive
way in which they said them …
It is,
therefore, necessary to be suspicious of those who seek to convince us with
means other than reason, and of charismatic leaders; we must be cautious about
delegating to others our judgement and our will. Since it is difficult to
distinguish between true prophets from false, it is well to regard all prophets
with suspicion. It is better to renounce revealed truths … It is better to
content oneself with more modest and less exciting truths … those than can be
verified and demonstrated.
[24]
In brief, reason is the only real
defence against fascism. But the ambivalent power relation of modern knowledge
remains problematic: knowledge is power-over and power-to. This leads to totalitarianism
or emancipation although the latter, too, is problematic: as in the dichotomy
between one model in which a chasm separates an old world from a new world which
arrives, as it were, from the sky, and another in which the world is made new
according to a design or intention produced in the old world, and is thereby shaped
to an extent by it.
[25]
It is impossible to escape the philosophical bind by which postmodernity is
shaped by modernity, or freedom by resistance to unfreedom.
It is possible, however, to argue, from Marx, that humans inflect the
trajectory, as said above. Then, modernity means contingency and this means in
turn that another world is always not only possible to imagine but also in the
making (although it may never reach a final stage).

Looking from within the glass house
Thinking of Clark’s statement, I
wonder if the argument that modernity has reached its end is extended or at
least affirmed by Sloterdijk’s claim that the project
of capital – also completed – is the total containment of the world.
Sloterdijk writes that capitalism’s shaping power had
always gone beyond the operations of the market, thus, ‘placing the entire
working life, wish life and expressive life … within the immanence of spending
power.
[26]
The figure of the globe acts to hold nations in a unified mass, and capital
possesses that whole Earth, its desires and cultures as well as work, so that
nothing – only, literally a void of outer space – is outside the
market’s containment mechanisms. A Soviet joke takes on a new meaning: using
the double meaning of the Russian word mir as Peace and Earth, it was said, we want Peace and we
want all of it. Capital substitutes Life for mir. This echoes sociologist Conrad Lodziak’s
argument that consumerism produces new human needs; these are really wants but
are experienced as new needs which compensate for the alienation and exhaustion
of routine toil.
[27]
Lodziak says that although consumers have agency, are not
completely duped by advertising, their agency is limited and hardly autonomous:
‘the consumer is … conceptualised as engaging in a form of active passivity.’
[28]
This is the context for a progressive (advancing in stages) appropriation of
the need for freedom and the experience of feeling free:
The
privatisation of freedom … refers to the conceptualisation of freedom in terms
of consumer choices. In the ideology of consumerism, consumer choices reflect
the interpretive freedom of the individual, and this is increasingly understood
as a freedom that is harnessed to the project of creating a self-identity. For
the New Right, the privatisation of freedom also refers … to the privatisation
of hitherto publicly provided … collective facilities, resources and services
that were available for everybody. Here privatisation means replacing state provision
with several competing service providers, and this alone is supposed to give
the consumer more choice.
[29]
Lodziak’s
description of consumerism appears to illustrate Sloterdijk’s
idea that a society’s working life, wish life and
expressive life are contained by the operations of global capital. I want to
make a further connection by comparing Lodziak’s
position with Herbert Marcuse’s argument that consumerism produces
contradictions which in turn produce new needs, but not passivity, rather liberational.
Marcuse says that the question, in
an affluent society, is no longer how an individual satisfies her or his needs
without hurting others but how she or he can satisfy these needs without an act
of self-harming (to paraphrase, avoiding Marcuse’s universal masculine) or, as
he puts it, ‘without reproducing [her/his] dependence on an exploitative
apparatus which … perpetuates [her/his] servitude.’
[30]
Marcuse continues that voluntary servitude can be ruptured only by, ‘a
political practice which reaches the roots of containment and contentment’
which means ‘a political practice of methodical disengagement’ leading to a
radical shift of values.
[31]
Then the question is how a vision of or desire for a qualitatively different
society is felt within existing conditions. Marcuse states the difficulty:
This is the
vicious circle: the rupture with the self-propelling conservative continuum of
needs must precede the revolution
which is to usher in a free society, but such rupture itself can be envisaged
only in a revolution – a revolution which would be driven by the vital
need to be freed from the administered comforts and the destructive
productivity of the exploitative society, freed from smooth heteronomy, a
revolution which, by virtue of this biological foundation, would have the
chance of turning quantitative technical progress into qualitatively different
ways of life … If this idea of a radical transformation is to be more than idle
speculation, it must have an objective foundation in the production process of
advanced industrial society …
[32]
His answer is that the
contradictions of capitalism themselves lead to the new biological need for
freedom which underpins a shift from quantitative to qualitative progress. If the
consumer economy and ‘the politics of corporate capitalism’ produce a ‘second
nature’ binding people ‘libidinally and aggressively
to the commodity form,’
[33]
then the alternative is glimpsed in the radical otherness of beauty, an
aesthetic universe which stands apart from consumerism and may have seemed,
momentarily, to appear in the events of May 1968 (or in student protests in
North America in the mid-1960s).
[34]
I have to leave the argument around beauty there.
[35]
Here the point is that Sloterdijk, Lodziak and Marcuse all propose a model of advanced
capitalism – for Sloterdijk a literally global
capitalism – which contains everything in its mechanisms of production-and-consumption.
Lodziak and Marcuse argue that human needs are
subsumed in an array of false wants designed to maintain an expanding market but
while Marcuse foresaw a new biological need for freedom from the affluent
society, Sloterdijk cites Dostoyevsky’s notes on the Great
Exhibition of 1851 at the Crystal Palace, London as a metaphorical-real model
of capital’s containment, looking to a new nihilism as the outcome:
… what spirals out of control in the capitalist world interior
is the inclination towards an end use devoid of ulterior motives; in the first
uproar a hundred years ago, this had been termed nihilism. The name expresses
the observation that consumption and disrespect are adjacent phenomena.
[36]
From this, perhaps, arises
ruin-lust, an addictive liking of fragments which is ambivalent: a reminder
that, in broken statues, power-over has declined; and a Romantic counter-force
to rationality as the quest for certainties (freedom from the vicissitudes of
Nature) which – ruins remind one in their disarray – are found only
in the self-contained systems of mathematics and geometry, in certain kinds of
philosophical logic, or in fancy. The message of a scene of ruins might also
be, however, that life goes on, something survives, and diverse energies seep
through the cracks. There may be a beach under the grey paving slabs; and there
is a potential for grass to grow between them.
[37]
Art may seem a vehicle for such seepage, but is it?

Looking at art
Thinking of Clark’s statement again
I find myself surrounded by signs of modernity’s end: the dereliction of
industry as material production moves to the South and is replaced in the North
by the fantasy realms of immaterial production and speculation in sectors such
as the media, advertising, public relations and financial services, called the
creative industries; the disempowering of trades unions, local government and
community groups, which stood for shared and civic interests; a systematic
dismantling of the welfare state. I am surrounded by ruins but are they, as
Brian Dillon suggests, ‘a warning for our own futures’ or do they allude unsettlingly
to, ‘a future past, the memory of what might have been’ in retro-futurism?
[38]
The ruin spellbinds in a reiteration of the past over which Fate presided; and
capital offers a no less enchanting apparatus of self-coercion, according to
philosopher Bernard Stiegler:
A prior,
spontaneous trust in the power of technological systems …which is the condition
of trust of consumers, as well as financial markets, and therefore investors,
is possible and conceivable only to the extent that everyone has an interest in the continuation of the functioning and
development of the system, even those for whom it does not yield any immediate
profit. We must all have a reason to
expect something from the functioning and development of the system, and
this reason to expect something can
only be the expectation of a better future.
[39]
A better future was the promise of
modernism. It failed because it was designed by experts to the exclusion of
vernacular knowledges, but this mismatch of ends and
means does not render the idea itself invalid. Modern art echoed modern architecture’s
reliance on expertise in an idea that avant-gardes can lead society in a new
direction, which implies that artists have a privileged insight into what that direction
is, and the power-over to lead people to it. Through the twentieth century, the
avant-garde was de-politicised, moving from Gustave
Courbet’s belief that art can change the world, after the 1848 revolution in
France, to oblique attacks on bourgeois culture’s institutions as a way to
undermine bourgeois social values; and in the 1960s a formalism in which
non-representational art erased narrative in a reductive revolution of styles.
Sloterdijk’s
idea of capital’s total containment is affirmed now as the art market subsumes
almost any departure into its mainstream. In the 1960s, artists refused to make
objects as art-commodities but dealers traded instead in reputations and glossy
colour books of photographs of ephemeralities. More
extremely, subsuming illegality, Tate Modern’s summer show, Street Art, in 2009 re-coded graffiti as
an art-commodity. Street artists were invited from around the globe to paint
panels affixed to the building’s exterior, sponsored by a Japanese car maker. In
a remaking of the wildlife safari by other means, guided walks around East
London enabled visitors to see street art in its natural surroundings. All this
marked the production of a new category, differentiated from the anti-social
activity of graffiti. so that it could be contained by
Contemporary Art. There was at least one international street art auction; another
auction house used the term urban art for a style based on street art where
none of the products were produced for street display.
[40]
Street art appears as good a case as any of Sloterdijk’s
picture of total containment. When an art form derived from illegal activity is
collectable, the project of containment may have no boundaries.

Looking at modernity’s beginnings
But if modernity’s dreams were
tarnished, it has been superseded by a bleaker world of ruins and lost hopes: a
realm of the peripheralisation and marginalisation of
social groups who are unwilling or unable to subscribe to brand-consumerism;
widening social divisions and deeper deprivation; and the precarity
of the flexible economy as a corrosion of skills and what was left of
satisfaction in labour.
[41]
Rather, however, than bewail the situation I want to ask again what it was
about modernity that leads me to feel a sense of loss at its passing, and what
among its traces might be extricated from the general mess to be reconsidered
and adapted for today.
Clark writes that modernity means
contingency, a social order which has replaced worship of ancestors and past
authorities with. ‘the pursuit of a projected future’
which also means, part and parcel, ‘a great emptying and sanitisation of the
imagination,’ in a disenchantment of the world.
[42]
The world’s disenchantment led at least one art critic to propose its
re-enchantment via art.
[43]
I argue against this elsewhere;
[44]
but
here I want to say briefly why I align myself to the disenchanted world of
modernity. Disenchantment means, to reiterate, emancipation from a world ruled
by Fate and watched over by ancestors. Modernity – as the experience of
being alive and conscious in a world in which the human subject has agency
– brings a promise of freedom and happiness; and entails the development
of ideas, perceptions and interpretations in shared logics through which to
arrive at common values. To recap again, disenchantment produces a search for
certainty in autonomous systems but most of life is neither geometrical nor
mathematical; hence quests for the ideal in which contingency is overcome are
theoretical limits rather than guides to everyday life. Modernity is learning
to live with uncertainties, an acceptance of uncertainty as an occupational
hazard which does not obliterate happiness but emphasises struggle. The alternative
is fear, and the twentieth century witnessed the effects of the charismatic
leaders who came to power through fear; that was what Levi wrote about. But
while the attraction of enchantment is maintained by consumerism – the goods
and services offered as a means to feeling that the subject has an identity are
alluring because most of the other operations of capital effectively deny that
identity through alienation, immiseration and precarity – it may be that Marcuse is accurate when
he looks to the inherent contradictions or illusions of the system to produce
resistance. I agree with Lodziak (above) that
consumers are not dupes, and may play games with the market; but Adorno’s view of the culture industry is as relevant now as
in the post-war period: ‘The dream industry does not so much fabricate the
dreams of the customers as introduce the dreams of the suppliers among the
people. This is the thousand-wear empire of an industrial caste system governed
by a stream of never ending dynasties.’
[45]
The art-world and fashion contain almost all departures (including styles which
emerge on the streets and are recycled as designer goods).
[46]
Myth is ended in Enlightenment yet returns in mass media and a vacuous politics
in which there is no alternative. But another world is possible, as proclaimed
at the World Social Forum in Port Alegre, Brazil in
2001.
[47]
Geographer Erik Swyngedouw
identifies an insurgent polis: ‘Rethinking … the “Right to the City” as the
“Right to the production of urbanisation”. Henri Lefebvre’s clarion call …
urges us to think of the city as a process of collective co-design and co-production.’
[48]
And this is not fanciful, but extant in numerous projects for intentional
communities since the 1960s, in eco-villages, in anti-capitalism and
single-issue campaigning, and most recently in Occupy. Although I am not an
activist – so was not there – Occupy suggests to me that it is
viable to make a new society within the old, if ephemerally and in ways which
are often compromised by circumstances. That is, the act of being there is the
enactment of alternative, life-affirming values. It is not to set up a signpost
to a proclaimed future like an avant-garde, but to be there, present in the
moment: a Lefebvrian moment which is brief yet
transformative. This is what I remember, if now at a distance, of anti-war and
anti-nuclear demonstrations in the late 1960s (when I was there); it is a form
of autonomy which is shared, a personal stance because the personal is
political and the political is personal, but not only that. It offers no
certainty, only hope.
In an interesting tangent, Bloch
refers to Joachim of Fiore and his contemporary Amalrich
of Bena as proclaiming a new world of the Spirit
which as both the end of a process of ‘degrees of illumination’ which is, in
effect, a deeply personal and introspective mysticism, and, at the same time without contradiction, ‘historical’ as, ‘the
light glows up three times, and it burns ever more precisely.’
[49]
Bloch sees a vile parody of the three ages in the Third Reich. He also reads a
projection of future, hoped-for worlds onto mythicized pasts: ‘The wish for
happiness was never painted onto an empty and completely new future. A better
past was always to be restored too, though not as a recent past, but that of a
dreamed-after, more beautiful earlier age.’
[50]
So, ‘We must repeatedly distinguish between mist and light … the impetus … of
these constructs is here likewise something different from the husk.’
[51]
Modernity conceals utopia and lent it forms no longer either realistic or
accessible; it was always ambivalent in an assertion of autonomy which could be
evolved as power-over or power-to; and it located humanity in a disenchanted
world where agency is always problematic but equally cannot be set aside in
favour of complicity. As a Socialist I cling to the vision of a better life for
all social classes which I read as the core content of modernism.
Born in 1950 during the Atlee
government, I lament the dismantling of the welfare state and trashing of the
public sector. I do not remember the Festival of Britain but it appears to have
been a nation-wide festival which was emblematic of a vision of rebuilding a
post-war world for the benefit of all social classes, linking culture,
technology and social equity. In contrast, the Millennium Dome was trash. If
the Great Exhibition represented Britain as a nation of manufacturers, however
contestably, the Dome told of celebrity and bling. As architectural historian
Simon Sadler observes, unlike the Festival of Britain, the Dome gave no sense
of a civic space. He adds, ‘The Dome’s spectacular failure underscrored
that in an age of flows, design cannot flow but must intervene … to create a
state of grace apart from pure economic exchange.’
[52]
I agree. Clark argues that modernism and socialism ended at the same time, and I
would add simply that, despite that, neither is over because a world of
contingency is a world-without-end.
[1]
The Invisible Collective, The Coming Insurrection, Los Angeles, Semiotext[e], 2009, p. 90
[2]
Cremmin,
C., Capitalism’s New Clothes: Enterprise,
Ethics and Enjoyment in Times of Crisis, London, Pluto, 2011, p. 15
[4]
Klein, N., No Logo, London, Flaqmingo, 2001; The Shock Doctrine, London, Penguin,
2007
[5]
Belsey,
C., The Subject of Tragedy: Identity and
Difference in Renaissance Drama, London, Routledge,
1985
[6]
Arnold, M., Culture and Anarchy [popular edition] London, Smith Elder, 1889, p.
36
[9]
Bloch, E., The Principle of Hope, Cambridge (MA), MIT, pp. 509-515
[10]
Bauman, Z., Globalization: The Human Consequences, Cambridge, Polity, 1998
[11]
Clark, T.J., Farewell to an Idea, New Haven (CT), Yale, 1999, p. 6
[12]
Dillon, B., Ruin Lust: Artists’ Fascination with Ruins from Turner to the Present
Day, London, Tate, 2014; Hell, J. and Schonle,
A., eds., Ruins of Modernity, Durham
(NC), Duke University Press, 2010
[14]
Sloterdijk,
P., In the Interior World of Capital,
Cambridge, Polity, 2013, p. 21
[17]
Adorno,
T.W. and Horkheimer, M., Dialectic of Enlightenment, [1944] London, Verso, 1997
[18]
Adorno and
Horkheimer, p. 38
[19]
Adorno and
Horkheimer, p. 41
[20]
Adorno and
Horkheimer, p. 42
[22]
See Bloch, E., Heritage of Our Times, Cambridge, Polity, 1991
[24]
Levi, P., If This Is a Man, London, Sphere, 1987, pp. 396-397
[25]
Laclau,
E., Emancipation(s), London, Verso,
1996, pp. 1-19
[27]
Lodziak,
C., The Myth of Consumerism, London,
Pluto, 2002
[28]
Lodziak,
p. 68, citing Gorz, A., Reclaiming Work: Beyond the Wage-based Society, Cambridge, Polity,
1999
[30]
Marcuse, H., An Essay on Liberation, Harmondsworth,
Penguin, 1969, p. 14
[35]
See Miles, M., Herbert Marcuse: an aesthetics of liberation, London, Pluto, 2011
[37]
See Wark, McK., The Beach
Beneath the Street: The everyday life and glorious times of the Situationist International, London, Verso, 2011
[39]
Stiegler,
B., Uncontrollable Societies of
Disaffected Individuals, Cambridge, Polity, 20134, p. 17
[40]
See Bengsten,
P., The Street Art World, Lund, Lund
University [PhD thesis], 2014
[41]
See Sennett, R., The Corrosion of Character, New York,
Norton, 1998; Hatherley, O., A Guide to the New Ruins of Great Britain, London, Verso, 2010, and
A New Kind of Bleak, London, Verso,
2012
[43]
Gablik,
S., The Reenchantment
of Art, London, Thames and Hudson, 1991
[44]
Miles, M., Eco-Aesthetics: Art, literature and architecture in a period of climate
change, London, Bloomsbury, 2014
[45]
Adorno,
T.W., ‘The schema of mass culture’, The
Culture Industry: Selected essays on mass culture, London, Routledge, 1991, p. 80
[46]
Zukin, S.,
The Cultures of Cities, Oxford,
Blackwell, 1995, p. 9
[47]
Houtart,
F. and Polet, F, Another
World is Possible: The Globalization of Resistance to the World economic System,
London, Zed Books, 2001
[48]
Swyngedouw,
E., Designing the Post-Political City and
the Insurgent Polis, Civic City Cahier 5, London, Bedford press, 2011, p.
53
[49]
Bloch, Heritage of Our Times, p. 124
[50]
Bloch, Heritage of Our Times, p. 128
[51]
Bloch, Heritage of Our Times, p. 136
[52]
Sadler, S., ‘Spectacular failure:
the architecture of late capitalism at the Millennium Dome’, Deamer, P., ed., Architecture
and Capitalism, 1845 to the present, London, Routledge,
2014, p. 199
|
|